홍어들아 내가 오죽하면 이런 글까지 쓰겠냐 이젠 처절하게 반성하고 사람답게 살아야 한다 전라도:) 

이젠 반성해야 한다, 너희는 절대선이 아니며 희생자도 더 이상 아니란 팩트:) 

나라망쳐 경제망쳐 결국 최악의 고통받는 건 너와 너가족이란 팩트:)

미국도 반미종북홍어와 민노총종북좌빨들은 더 이상 유학 취업 장기체류 이민등 받아주지 않는 다는 팩트:) 


///////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////

밑의 Article의 핵심은 The Left (좌파, 좌빨, ㅅㅂ 좌좀= 떼홍어 etc 여러형태로 표현되는 통칭 좌파들은) 

행동심리학적으로 살면살수록 가난해지는 건 팩트란 것:) 


불평등을 떠들면서 점점 더 불평등한 사회구조를 만들어가는 좌파들:) 

확률적으로 100%에 가깝다는 수학적팩트:) 

좃병신 홍어들 한국경제 1분기에 이어 2분기에도 사상초유의 연속 (-)경제성장하면 볼만하겠군:)


내가 오죽하면 안토니오 그람시 (문재앙 조국 임종석 이인영 이해찬 박원숭등 좃병신 좌빨들이 좋아하는)  공산주의자의 말까지 인용했겠냐?:)

즉 저 개쓰레기들은 절대 공산주의자조차도 못된다는 팩트:)

 

안토니오 그람시가 뭐라디? 공산주의 헤게모니의 핵심은 '스스로 동의 하는 지배' 라고 했다는 팩트:)  

그게 공산주의란 이념의 헤게모니의 핵심이라고 했다는 팩트:) 


'스스로 동의하는 지배는 오직 (개개인이) 자유'  뿐이라고  20세기 초 레닌이 극찬하고 러시아여성들의 숭고한 모델이여야 한다고 극찬한 

유명한 여성공산주의자 로사룩셈부르크가 자신을 극찬한 레닌을 신랄하게 비판하면 이런 말을 했다! 


'레닌! 혁명 후 당신이 말하는 자유는 자신과 생각이 다른 이들을 위한 자유가 아닌 

군림하기 위한 볼세비키와 그 당중앙 당신만의 자유, 그 자유는 또 다른 짜르의 탄생일 뿐이요' 


자 이제 알겠냐?  인류를 관통하는 유일한 가치는 바로 개개인의 자유, 즉 다름에 대한 자유란 팩트:)

스스로 동의하는 지배는 바로 (개인의 )자유밖에 없단 팩트:) 군중의 집단의 = 광장의 집단적 자유가 아니란 팩트:) 


개쓰레기 '군중이란 집단의 비겁함속에 숨은 철저한 파시스트들의 모습' (하버마스 극좌파비판) = 파시스트 쓰레기 전라도! 


아 졸라 바쁜데 또 시간 여기서 휘리릭 나중에:) 


///////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////

미리 전문적인 내용이라고 말했다:) 

미개한 좌빨들이라고 쓰고 홍어들이라고 읽는 다는 팩트:) 

하긴 니들하고 이런 Math & Rational Thinking 적 토론은 할수가 없지:)


달리 좌빨이겠냐 정신병자란 팩트:) 


Are We Too Irrational for Rawls’ Veil of Ignorance?

Posted onMay 9, 2019 by Sean Yun


The veil of ignorance, proposed in John Rawls’ 1971 book, A Theory of Justice, is a key concept in the liberal pursuit of a just society. Rawls suggests that, when building a society, we should place ourselves behind a veil of ignorance, which prevents us from knowing our place in that society: as far as we can tell, we will be randomly assigned a position in the society we build. Rawls asserts that, when comparing two societies, the more just society would be the one into which we are more willing to be placed without knowing our position within it beforehand. A just society is “a society that if you knew everything about it, you’d be willing to enter it in a random place.”

This, Rawls argues, inevitably leads self-concerned (and, according to Rawls’ more utilitarian followers, rational) beings to construct a welfare state, in which individuals cannot fall into poverty, even if that means that it is harder to amass extreme wealth. However, humans are not rational, self-concerned beings, and it is not at all clear that the veil of ignorance would lead people to construct an egalitarian society. Key insights from decision science can help us understand how people might think under a veil of ignorance, and why.

This article will rely on prospect theory, for which Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky won the Nobel Prize in economics in 2002. This theory came to replace the previously widely held view of human beings as rational economic agents (Homo economicus), who deal with probabilities and consequences in a mathematically consistent and value-maximizing way. While prospect theory has been falsified, in the sense that there are economic behaviors that deviate from its predictions, its insights into people’s understanding of extremely high and low probabilities, and the importance of reference points, are well established.

The Probability Weighting Function

First, let us imagine a situation in which a loved one takes a flight, on which there is a 1% chance that the plane will crash, killing said loved one. How much are you willing to pay to remove the 1% chance of a crash, thus increasing the probability of a safe flight from 0.99 to 1? And, in a different scenario, how much would you pay to increase the probability of a safe flight from 0.5 to 0.51? If you are like most people, you are willing to pay quite a lot to reach certainty, but you don’t value the change from 50% to 51% nearly as much. This is hardly rational, in a mathematical sense, since a change from 0.5 to 0.51 has the same value as a change from 0.99 to 1. Even economists tend to overvalue certainty. This is known as the certainty effect.

The flipside of our tendency to overvalue certainty is our tendency to overvalue low probabilities, a phenomenon known as the possibility effect. For example, how much are you willing to pay for a probability of 0.001, as opposed to 0, of winning a million dollars in the lottery? And how much are you willing to pay to change the probability from 0.5 to 0.501? The way that people value a 0.001 change in probability is not constant: many of those who regularly bet on the lottery assign too much value to the mere possibility of winning.



Dopamine D-1 Receptors and Nonlinear Probability Weighting in Risky Choice (Takahashi et al)

So, how do people’s evaluations of probabilities affect their decisions under a veil of ignorance? Let’s imagine we are asked to choose between two societies in which 1000 utility points are distributed among 100 people. In one society, all the points are distributed roughly equally, whereas the other society roughly follows a Pareto distribution, in which many people have few or no utility points, while a few people have most of the points. Rawls would expect people to prefer the egalitarian society, since they would not wish to have few or no utility points, i.e. to live in extreme poverty. However, people might overvalue the possibility, however unlikely, of having many utility points—of being extremely wealthy—because they put too much value on the mere possession of this possibility.

The Reference-Based Value Function

Further complications arise from the role of reference points in people’s understanding of economic consequences. Rawls assumes that people are concerned about becoming impoverished, which should lead them to prefer a welfare state. Alternatively, the utilitarian analysis of economic consequences, adopted by some of Rawls’ followers, follows a diminishing utility pattern, meaning that the more you have of something, the less you are affected by a unit change in that thing. Put more concretely, a penniless individual values an increase of 50 dollars to his wealth much more than a billionaire would. As such, rational individuals should prefer avoiding poverty (where every utility point counts) to having the chance of becoming extremely wealthy (where utility points have highly diminished value). By contrast, prospect theory suggests that people’s preferences are relative, not absolute—we don’t just evaluate the sum of utility points, and then apply a diminishing value function; rather, we compare consequences to a reference point, and evaluate them in different ways, depending on how they deviate from that reference. A reference-based analysis from beneath the veil of ignorance might diverge from Rawls’ emphasis on the fear of becoming impoverished.

To illustrate the importance of reference points, let’s consider a classical experimental paradigm. Imagine I give you 50 dollars and then I ask you to bet on a coin toss: if the coin comes up heads, you give me 25 dollars, whereas you will earn a certain amount of money if the coin comes up tails. What is the minimum amount of reward money it would take for you to accept the bet? Now imagine instead that I told you that I am going to give you 50 dollars in five minutes time, but first I give you the chance to take the same bet. How much reward money would it take for you to accept the bet?

If you randomly assign people to two groups, and ask one group of people to bet under the first circumstance, and the other to bet under the second, you get very different patterns. People who bet money they see as their own are much more hesitant to lose it, and need a much bigger incentive to be persuaded to take the bet. This is because they frame their current financial situation as a reference, from which a lost bet would lead to a loss, whereas winning the bet would lead to a gain. By contrast, those who are told they will be given 50 dollars in the future are already in a framework of gain, whether or not they win the bet. This matters, because people are much more sensitive to losses than to gains. This is called loss aversion, and it is the main reason for the importance of reference points in prospect theory. (add graph of the value function?)



Value Function of a Prospect Theory Model. Source: Jacob and Ehret 2006

So why does reliance on references matter under the veil of ignorance? Rawls expects people to ignore their circumstances when judging a society, and focus on avoiding the risk of poverty. However, under a veil of ignorance, a poor person is unlikely to judge a society in the same way a wealthy person would, because he does not use absolute metrics, but, instead, his own reference points.

Prospect Theory Under a Veil of Ignorance

Most human societies, both now and in the past, have tended to have a roughly Pareto distribution. Large swathes of a society often possess only a little of its wealth.



By Wikideas1 – Own work https://apps.urban.org/features/wealth-inequality-charts/, CC0, https://commons.wikimedia.org/w/index.php?curid=70500652

One observation that baffles political commentators is that many in the lower classes tend to vote for political parties that maintain the unequal status quo, rather than promote economic equality. This is often described as voting against one’s own interests. However, prospect theory suggests that this is more complicated than it seems. Perhaps people resist high taxes for the super rich because they overestimate their likelihood of becoming rich, owing to the status quo-justifying belief that anyone can make it if they work hard enough. This effect will not be fully undone by a veil of ignorance, since the overvaluing of extremely low probabilities still applies. Furthermore, when a poor person is placed under the veil, and asked to consider being assigned a random position in one of the two societies, he brings his reference with him. As such, he is likely to consider the egalitarian society as a certain, moderate gain, and overestimate the low probability of becoming wealthy in the non-egalitarian society, while remaining relatively insensitive to the prospect of poverty. Under these circumstances, is it really surprising that a poor person under the veil might choose to bet on the unequal society? After all, what has he got to lose? By contrast, a middle-class man would pick an egalitarian society when under the veil, due to loss aversion, evoked by the possibility of living in poverty in an unequal society. This could be exacerbated by his overvaluation of the certainty of avoiding poverty, and the diminishing returns of becoming super-wealthy. Interestingly, this middle-class perspective is quite similar to the loss averse answer Rawls envisages. A very wealthy person might also prefer the unequal society, since, while both evoke strong loss aversion, the unequal society allows for the (overvalued) possibility of maintaining one’s wealth.

Human psychology undermines the key purpose of the veil of ignorance: namely, to allow individuals to judge a society independently of their current situations. Even Rawls might not be able to avoid these effects, since his own perspective may be the result of his socioeconomic background. While the rational, utilitarian choice under the veil of ignorance is equality, it seems unlikely that people under the veil would make rational evaluations. Thus, the veil of ignorance might be mostly effective in convincing middle-class individuals to support welfarism, because of people’s class-dependent reference points, and the way they evaluate extreme probabilities.